A simpler, more elegant, route to communism

An increasing number of folks have been raising the question about hours of labor and the problem of what David Graeber called “bullshit jobs”. vietnamsI have spent some time on the subject in the past few months, but feel it necessary to return to the question again, since I have just come across a paper appearing to refute the idea. The paper by the bourgeois simpleton economist, Axel Borsch-Supan, purports to lay out the argument against a reduction of hours of labor. It is an interesting read because the guy, who is clearly an opponent of reducing hours of labor, thinks he can be trusted to state the case on its behalf.

And, bizarrely enough, instead of refuting the idea, Borsch-Supan actually may have ended up making an argument on its behalf.

The question, as he very narrowly defines it, is this: Can fewer hours of labor reduce unemployment? He begins the effort to find an answer to this question by setting out “the theoretical background of the debate in order to isolate the main mechanisms that might create (or inhibit) positive employment effects in response to an hours reduction. ”

However his argument against fewer hours of labor comes down to exactly one point: The amount of labor is not given as a fixed lump which can only be redistributed among a given number of workers. According to Borsch-Supan, the case for hours of labor reduction hinges on the so-called lump of labor fallacy. This alleged fallacy states there is a fixed amount of labor required for production of commodities, which can be divided among the total available workers in the market for labor power, both employed and unemployed, simply by reducing the hours of labor of the employed. If the total labor requirement of production is fixed, reducing labor for employed workers will increase the demand for the labor of the unemployed.

Of course, no one actually uses the above argument, but people who support the reduction of hours of labor are regularly accused of committing the fallacy. But this is not because proponents of shorter hours employ this fallacy — instead, the lump of labor fallacy figures in the debate simply because the opponents of reduced labor hours have no other argument on which to rest their case than to state the proponents of shorter hours of labor are engaged in a fallacy.

Having identified a straw man position as his opponent, Borsch-Supan argues the employment effect of reducing hours of labor has a fatal flaw: the amount of labor needed is not fixed.

“While the often-voiced first-round theoretical argument – less work for some must create more work for others – appears “obvious” in favor of a positive employment effect, it has several major flaws. First, the amount of labor is not given as a fixed lump which can only be redistributed. The total amount of labor demanded and supplied changes as the economy evolves, and a reduction of working time may affect this total amount of labor. Thus, partial analysis of the labor market needs to be supplemented by a general equilibrium analysis of total demand in the economy.”

Which is to say, while it might appear hours of labor are fixed, once legally mandated hours are reduced, other changes occur in the “economy” that can significantly reduce the need for labor. For example, as Borsch-Supan tells us, once the legal maximum hours of labor are reduced, the capitalist must choose between bearing the increased cost of labor or replacing a portion of his work force with machines, etc.

The so-called lump of labor fallacy runs into an additional problem: while reducing hours of labor might open up new jobs to be filled, the skills of the unemployed workers may not be sufficient to fill those positions. Useful labor is not homogenous. To give an extreme example: someone trained adequately to flip burgers at McDonald’s is not necessarily qualified to run a nuclear power plant.

Finally, according to Borsch-Supan, the proponents of labor hours reduction conflate hours of labor needed with number of people need to work those hours. Since a legal maximum on hours of labor only constrains employers, it is possible that some workers may wish to work longer than the legally mandated maximum hours of labor — they may, for instance, choose to do voluntary overtime for their existing employer or even work a second job.

Borsch-Supan’s argument against reducing hours of labor thus rests on the argument that any such reduction will have little or no effect on the rate of unemployment. But, of course, hours of labor reduction doesn’t just hinge on its employment effect: Fewer hours of labor is (in bourgeois simpleton parlance) a “good” in and of itself. If we can reduce hours of labor by fifty percent and still produce the same output as at present, who cares about the employment effect?

Employment is an important consideration  for reducing hours of labor, but it is not the only consideration in the argument — nor is it the most important consideration. Assuming six percent unemployment, if after reducing hours of labor by 50% we still have six percent unemployment, who is going to complain? The 94% of the workers who have jobs now need only work 20 hours per week instead of 40. BS makes it appear that reducing hours of labor is a failure if no reduction in unemployment is achieved when people now only have to work 20 hours a week

The core fallacy for reducing hours of labor, Borsch-Supan explains, rests on the Keynesian assumption that wages and prices are sticky — that is, the owners of commodities will try to resist any fall in wages paid for labor power or the prices of other commodities. If wages and prices are sticky, as the Keynesians argue, a legally mandated reduction in hours of wage labor will lead to a proportional increase in employment, and total worker-hours remain constant.

Or so the argument goes.

Of course, this Keynesian assumption is silly, but can the argument for reducing hours of labor only be made on the basis of an assumption that wages and prices are sticky? Further, do we have to hold to the idea that the need for labor is constant and unchanging (the “lump of labor fallacy”)? Suppose we assume the opposite case: If hours of labor are reduced, the need for labor will fall and, moreover, wages and prices will decline as well.

These two assumptions are not the least bit Keynesian — they are the assumptions of labor theory of value.

According to labor theory if hours of labor are reduced, wage and prices and the need for labor fall more rapidly. The labor theory argument is based on a simple assumption: as hours of labor are reduced, the demand for labor power will be reduced as well, because the capitalist class now has an added incentive to introduce improved machinery, technology, scientific know-how and better organization of the labor process to replace labor whenever the legal hours of labor are cut. Beginning from the opposite assumption of the “lump of labor” fallacy, we arrive at the reality that capital is compelled by a reduction of hours of labor to develop the productive forces.

This particular argument is actually 150 years old and can be found in Marx’s Capital, volume one:

“The shortening of the hours of labour creates, to begin with, the subjective conditions for the condensation of labour, by enabling the workman to exert more strength in a given time. So soon as that shortening becomes compulsory, machinery becomes in the hands of capital the objective means, systematically employed for squeezing out more labour in a given time. This is effected in two ways: by increasing the speed of the machinery, and by giving the workman more machinery to tent. Improved construction of the machinery is necessary, partly because without it greater pressure cannot be put on the workman, and partly because the shortened hours of labour force the capitalist to exercise the strictest watch over the cost of production. “

Thus, reducing hours of labor works three ways according to Marx: the performance of the workers are improved, because they are better rested; improved machinery are introduced; and the efficiency in the use of capital is increased. In fact, Marx concluded that it was the shortening of hours of labor that made England into an industrial superpower in the 19th century:

“There cannot be the slightest doubt that the tendency that urges capital, so soon as a prolongation of the hours of labour is once for all forbidden, to compensate itself, by a systematic heightening of the intensity of labour, and to convert every improvement in machinery into a more perfect means of exhausting the workman, must soon lead to a state of things in which a reduction of the hours of labour will again be inevitable. On the other hand, the rapid advance of English industry between 1848 and the present time, under the influence of a day of 10 hours, surpasses the advance made between 1833 and 1847, when the day was 12 hours long, by far more than the latter surpasses the advance made during the half century after the first introduction of the factory system, when the working-day was without limits.”

So, in labor theory, reduction of hours of labor not only accelerates the development of the productive forces, with this development of the productive forces successive reductions of labor becomes becomes necessary: it “must soon lead to a state of things in which a reduction of the hours of labour will again be inevitable.”

Which is to say, reducing hours of labor first and foremost accelerates the demise of capitalism and wage slavery — freeing up disposable time for the great majority of society.

8 thoughts on “A simpler, more elegant, route to communism”

  1. I think the argument that mandatory reduction of hours may help to liberate workers is flawed.

    The problem concerns the disposition of the unpaid hours of wage slaves. The essay assumes that if a worker’s hours are not spent working for wages, then they are “free time” or “disposable time”, available for the worker to use for himself outside the wage system.

    Speaking very abstractly, the unpaid hours do not become the workers’ if these three conditions all hold:

    (a) the workers are still dependent on wages for survival;

    (b) capitalists are able to impose conditions which make worker access to wages contingent about the worker making certain uses of those hours

    (c) the constraints on worker use of supposed “free” time are necessary but not sufficient conditions upon access to wages

    In other words, just as in paid work the capitalist gets to tell the worker how to spend this time; if the worker refuses he will have no access to wages; if the worker obeys he might but is not guaranteed access to wages.

    If there is a capitalist advantage to creating conditions like those, then a reduction of hours is not a step away from wage slavery for workers.

    What would those abstract conditions look like in a concrete setting?

    First a straw-man:

    Capitalists could, let’s say, try to make sure that much of everyone’s time spent away from wage work is spent in prison.

    Workers would still depend on wages for their time away from prison which satisfies condition (a).

    Capitalists would only hire workers not in prison, which satisfies condition (b).

    Capitalists would not have to guarantee all released workers employment, satisfying (c).

    I called this a “straw man” concretization of the idea because I don’t mean to claim this is how we should understand, for example, the high incarceration rate in the U.S. Generally, I don’t see any capitalist advantage to trying to imprison workers that way.

    Is there a more realistic concretization? I speculate there is, along these lines:

    I don’t know for sure but I don’t think Marx anticipated modern technologies of mass surveillance, enchantment, and targeted interventions.

    Today, capitalists are able to direct the construction of massive webs of surveillance that turn mass surveillance data into a valued commodity. The worker is increasingly subject to constant monitoring, even while not on the job.

    Capitalists are able to unprecedented degrees to influence the off-hours behavior of workers with enchanting spectacles (ubiquitous “screens”, ear-buds, a constant barrage of dazzlement) and with individualized interventions (targeted ads, monitoring by police forces, “personalized” experiences as an essential component of consumption).

    Capitalists can and we’ve seen do use mass surveillance to impose necessary though not sufficient conditions on worker access to wages.

    At least for now it appears that capitalists find considerable advantage in taking over worker free time this way. It helps create efficiencies of selling just what they want to sell; obtaining higher rents; and grooming workers for docile conformity.

    To anticipate and repsond to one possible objection:

    I’m don’t think this situation can be attributed to the individual “bad choices” of workers. That assumes that their participation in and submission to the disciplinary system of surveillance, enchantment, and personalized intervention is both (a) individual; (b) voluntary.

    That participation in the system is manipulated by capitalists to constrain one’s possible places in the pecking order of wage slaves means that the system is not voluntary.

    Because the system individualizes workers and compares surveillance data from one against another, it helps to impose a condition of competition on wage workers even during their “free” hours — so the system is not individual.

    Does this mean that it is bad to push for a public policy to legislate a mandatory reduction in hours?

    It certainly suggests such a push isn’t automatically good and that it might be bad in the sense of helping to reinforce a veil over workers’ eyes as to what “free” time is coming to mean.

    Like

    1. Perhaps you are right, but I was thinking more along the lines of a three day workweek that replaces the five day workweek we have now. Do the capitalists tell you how to use your weekends? 🙂

      Like

    2. I would just like to input, that the power of this malevolent surveillance arm you describe finds considerably less funding after a reduction in labour time.
      I do not believe it to be the case that the state can truly influence any social relation, it can only utilise the existing relations.

      Like

    3. How do you find time to critique capitalist “bedazzlement” when every second of our lives is systematically over-determined by the interests of Capital? Like seriously, and not just to razz you, but how can you possibly believe that when your own writing about it, reading about it, communicating about it (hopefully more broadly than online, which I know can be tough) concretely contradicts it. Or are you an absurdist comment artist?

      Hopefully I can be authentic about how frustrating your manner of totalizing the issue is and you can take me as asking you earnest questions that vex me in my real, stupid life, because what I see you purporting is another version of cynicism.

      It is not that I don’t see how one can pick and choose from “the [largely online] culture” things to support the view that how we spend our times reflect capitalist priorities. It is not that I am not aware that we feed our bodies as part of a life process currently colonized by the wage-system.

      My frustration is the way that your way of putting this subtly naturalizes capital in everyday life as a concretized and unassailable totality, despite I think being motivated against this transformation. Part of it is, I think, that it reflects a weird way of aligning one’s thinking with those of the policy makers and technocrats. Maybe this is because, it is thought, that if any such radical reforms were to be enacted it’d only be because of those with state-power, who are themselves only really motivated by what stabilizes the capitalist economy. At any rate, you’d think that workers weren’t also already talking about and thinking in terms of reduced work hours, social security for all, socialized medicine. It’s not the dominant culture in American media, but not all workers are robots or the programmed consumers, even those who haven’t read a lick of Marx.

      Like

      1. Hi, Joe. I don’t think I’m being cynical or engaging in performance art. I understand (or maybe misunderstand) Jehu to be developing a theoretical case meant to serve as a foundation for a practical political program of pushing for a reduction of hours. There are questions activists face like: What’s the effect of pushes to raise the minimum wage? or What’s would be the effect o a push for a 20 hr work week? I’m starting from the assumption that Jehu is offering up some theory for questions like that.

        I think I see some problems with the theory of hours reduction as Jehu is developing it. Not that I think it’s completely wrong (or completely right) but I think there are problematic aspects.

        One of those problematic areas concerns how capital adapts to a reduction in hours.

        For Marx, capital responds with investment in industrial machinery that ultimately alters the organic composition of capital by technical means.

        I think capital today has degrees of freedom that were inconceivable to Marx — particularly capital’s freedoms related to the emerging ubiquity of surveillance and the insinuation of “high tech” intermediation of economic and social relations.

        I do not think that the “disciplinary state with fur-line handcuffs” traps being laid for the proletariat are inescapable. On the other hand, I don’t see much escaping going on.

        I don’t claim to definitively know whether a political push for hours reduction is a good idea but I have some concern because of these new high-tech responses capital can muster to maintain discipline, alter consumption patterns, distract from situational awareness, and so on.

        I sometimes read the silicon valley trade press and related publications. Some of what I read sticks out at me in this context:

        (a) Capitals who are wondering in print how to make a high tech means of exchange and distribution for our post-labor, robots-are-our-slaves future. They are eagerly anticipating a reduction in hours.

        (b) Capitals active and eager to essentially dismantle public education and replace it mostly with narrow vocational preparation.

        (c) Capitals (ostensibly) fascinated by concepts like “sharing economy”, “gift economy”, “gamification”, etc.

        (d) Capitals highly defensive of the peonage of the proletariat which they describe as a simple system of “meritocracy”.

        (e) Capitals eager to make computing-related and network-related relations ubiquitous while at the same time pushing ever harder for computing hardware and networks over which “users” — the workers — have no power. Examples include: celebrations of the purported death of the personal computer (in favor of centralized network services); and the “jailing” of mobile devices to prevent users from running software not approved by a corporate overseer.

        A political push for a reduction of hours seems to me to risk fueling that fire of current trends. There may be better strategies for working to end capital’s binders.

        Like

  2. “capitalists are able to impose conditions which make worker access to wages contingent about the worker making certain uses of those hours”

    Aren’t these “free” hours then just work by another name? What is the distinction between contracted work for wages & other required activity for wages?

    What you are describing is certainly true – the social labor of Facebook, etc. and cultural labor of television events and so on are very much worth noting. But it seems to me those should be considered work as much as actual “time on the job” – unproductive labor to be sure, but that fits with what Jehu has argued – the need to produce more and more unproductive labor.

    (I wonder if we might look at this as a possible explanation of the apparent huge overvaluation of tech services like Facebook and Twitter, who produce very little revenue compared to their valuations with stock prices and such – perhaps those valuations are recognition of the services they provide in consuming worker time.)

    Like

    1. about: “I wonder if we might look at this as a possible explanation of the apparent huge overvaluation of tech services like Facebook and Twitter, who produce very little revenue compared to their valuations”

      I’m interested in the internal rate of profit (in the sense of p/(c+v)) for Google in relation to ads and the related services like gmail, g+, docs, and so forth. I suspect it is outrageously high.

      Like

Leave a comment

This site uses Akismet to reduce spam. Learn how your comment data is processed.